“Liberalism was, in origin, criticism of the old
established order. Today, it is the voice of the establishment.”
--George Grant
“The end is in the beginning.”
--Plato
“I have found from many observations that sometimes
our liberal is incapable of granting anyone else his own convictions and
immediately answers his opponent with abuse or something worse.”
--Dostoyevsky
“The saint needed by each culture is the one who
contradicts it the most.”
--G.K. Chesterton
1.
The Matrix of Liberalism
All of us, whether we are
consciously aware of it or not, think from a core of philosophic principles. It
is from these seed thoughts, principles or ideas, that the fruit of various and
varied ethical positions are taken. We live in a period of time in which many
ethical positions are embraced, contested and questioned in our culture wars.
Many is the hot button issue that, when articulated and argued in the public
places, creates many a reaction. Ethical tribes and clans (and chieftains
aplenty) have emerged to beat the drums for ethical positions on the political
right, sensible centre and political left.
If we
are ever going to come to a serious and substantive dialogue about both the
roots and fruits of ethical positions, we do need to nudge the discussion to a
much deeper level. It does little good to argue the case pro-contra of
abortion, euthanasia, death penalty, traditional family values, militarism,
market economy, globalization, environmental concerns, gay rights, drugs,
stronger state-lighter state, religious pluralism and many other issues if we
do not understand the principles that animate and predefine the positions taken
before they are taken.
We do
need to turn, therefore, to the question of principles, prejudices,
presuppositions, and ideas before we venture into the controversial hot button
ethical issues. Just as an acorn becomes an oak tree, a sunflower seed becomes
a sunflower plant, a colt a horse, a calf a cow, a baby a teen and adult, so,
in seed form, it is principles that bud, blossom and bear fruit in the area of
ethical issues.
We all
know that taking a lawnmower over a field of dandelions does not get rid of the
dandelions. The mower will cut off the yellow head of the dandelions, but, a
few weeks later, the roots will produce yet another yellow field of dandelions.
It is from the roots that the flower is produced, and if we are not pleased
with the flower (be it weed or flower), we must take the time to dig up the
roots. The same analogy could be applied to fruit on a tree. A tree might
produce good, bad or mediocre fruit. It is rather pointless, though, to think
that by throwing away bad fruit on a tree (or blaming the fruit that is
produced) that the tree will then produce a harvest of fine fruit. If the fruit
is bad, then it is important to check out the soil, the inner life of the tree,
the sap and deeper roots.
There
is no doubt we live in an age dominated by liberalism. The principles,
prejudices and premises of liberalism are the creed and dogma of the time. It
is virtually impossible in our age and time to think outside of the matrix of
liberal ideas. The hot button issues in the culture wars often favour those who
are apologists of the liberal way and sway. If we, for the most part, are born
and bred in the liberal matrix, what is the nature of this matrix, and how does
it shape, socialize and predefine how we should think on a variety of ethical
and metaphysical questions? And, more importantly, is it possible to think
outside of this intellectual matrix? If not, have we not set ourselves up for a
benign form of totalitarianism or soft despotism? It is ironic that many
liberals hold a high view of reason and critical thinking, but they seem
incapable of being critical of the principles of liberalism.
We are
very much in the matrix of liberalism at the present time, and we do need, if
we are ever going to be minimally thoughtful and critical, to ask ourselves
this rather simple and elementary question: what is the appeal and limitation
of liberalism? If we are only boosters or knockers of the liberal project, we
become reactionaries and ideologues. If and when we ponder the sic et non (yes and no) of the liberal agenda, we can open our
minds to examine a fuller way of thinking and living.
II. The Principles of Liberalism
The matrix if liberalism,
as I mentioned above, is founded and grounded on certain principles, ideas,
worldviews, prejudices, and presuppositions. These principles are not new, but
they do dominate, define and enframe most of the modern dialogue on ethical
issues. What are these principles, what are the historic roots of such
principles, and what is both the strength (appeal) and limitation (dark sides)
of such ideas? Richard Weaver had a book published a few years ago called Ideas
Have Consequences (1948). Whether we agree with all of Weaver’s arguments is
not the point here, but Weaver is right when he argues that ideas do have
consequences. Ideas (or principles) do lead to decisions, and decisions have
consequences in both a personal and public way. Therefore, it is to the level
to ideas (principles) we must turn to make sense of how the oak tree of ethical
issues is but the consequence of the small acorn of certain philosophical
principles.
What,
then, are the principles from which the liberal project emerges? There is
little doubt that liberalism tends to accept and embrace the principles of
liberty (freedom), individualism, equality, fraternity (solidarity),
conscience, historicism and the quest for meaning, happiness or authenticity.
These principles, of course, can be priorized in different ways, and as they
are priorized in a different way, different forms and types of liberalism will
emerge. Those who priorize liberty will be suspicious of any form of state or
community interference with individual longings and desires in either the
social or economic sphere. Those who priorize fraternity (solidarity) will
attempt to curtail some individual rights so that all may have their liberty
enhanced. The Liberal project, as a way of knowing, can elevate reason and
critical thinking over and against intuition and imagination or imagination in
opposition to reason. It is this debate that has defined and shaped the
rationalist-romantic dialogue within the liberal clan and family.
The
actual content of what is known and ethical positions taken in the liberal
project are quite secondary to the principles that are accepted by faith and
are the dominant creed and dogma of liberalism. Liberal principles are like a
sacred and time tried vase and container that will be protected at all costs.
The actual liquid that is poured into the vase is not of primary importance. It
is more important that liberty, individuality and equality are protected than
defining how liberty, equality and individuality are to be defined. Each and
all, within the liberal ideal, should and can use such principles as they see
fit to serve and suit their own journey for meaning and happiness, and, of
course, these terms, are open to be defined by the individual.
If
liberal principles can be seen, in some sense, as the trunk that steadies and
does much to produce the fruit of liberal ethical issues, the deeper and more
demanding roots of the liberal way take us to the liberal notion of human
nature. Human nature, within the liberal tradition, tends to be open and weak
on boundaries and limitations. Human nature is a project in which we make
ourselves. Just a painter creates a work of art on a blank canvass, a poet
creates a poem on an empty piece of paper, the liberal notion of human nature
tends to see the human journey as open ended. There is no doubt we have
desires, longings, hopes and dreams, passions and hungers, but the way we
direct, form, shape and heed such longings is as open as there are
possibilities to experiment with. We are products of time and history
(historicism), and who is to say what is the best way to live?
It is
this liberal notion of human nature coupled with the liberal notion of
historicism that is the deeper roots of the liberal tradition and creed. The
matrix of liberalism, when probed at the level of human nature and historicism,
takes us to the heart, core and centre of the liberal project. Where did such
ideas come from that so dominate our age and ethos, and can they be questioned?
In fact, dare they be questioned? More worrisome, though, what happens when we
dare not question such principles and ideas? But, let us turn to the historic
roots of the liberal way. Ideas often take centuries to fully work and play
themselves out, and this is just as true of liberalism as any other ideological
and intellectual system.
III.
The Historic Drama of Liberalism:
A Seven-Act Play
Many has been the debate
about the historic beginnings of liberalism. There are those who are keen on
taking the dialogue about the origins of liberalism back to the Classical era.
Plato and Aristotle are pitted against one another, and Plato is seen as the
conservative and Aristotle is viewed as the liberal. There were, obviously,
differences between Plato and Aristotle, but both men did participate within
the Classical understanding of what it means to be human. Both men viewed
contemplation as higher than action, and both men were grounded in the notion
of natural law, and the idea that all things have a proper purpose and end
(telos), and to the degree all things moved towards such an end, the good life
would be realized and actualized. The virtues-vices played an important role in
giving shape and form to such an end, and a person was only free to the degree
they lived within such a form and structure. There is no doubt that Plato had a
greater interest in metaphysics and dialogue as a way of knowing, but he was
also most concerned about politics and economics. Aristotle lingered longer on
questions of logic, science and the inductive way (which Plato saw as a lower
way of knowing and being), but both men accepted the fact there was an order in
the cosmos, and to the degree each and all knew such an order and attuned and
aligned themselves with it, they would be free. It is only in a suggestive
sense that we can argue that the origins of liberalism can be found in
Aristotle, but many is the American and European republican that will attempt
to track and trace the liberal republican way back to Aristotle, Seneca and
Cicero.
The
painting by Raphael, The School of Athens, depicts Plato and Aristotle entering
a large room, and Plato pointing to the heights and Aristotle to the firm earth
below distorts the insights of both men. Plato and Aristotle sought to
integrate both eternity and time, metaphysics and ethics in their way of
thinking. The Medieval era tended to be more indebted to Plato than Aristotle,
but by the High Middle Ages, Aristotle began to make a return. The beginning of
liberalism, I think, can be tracked to the latter half of the Middle Ages.
The
shift in philosophy from an interest in universals to particulars signaled this
beginning. This is Act One in the west of liberalism. With the rise of
nominalism, we begin to see more emphasis on the individual, on the particular.
This was but a seed tossed into the soil of thought, but seeds, in time, do
break through their constrictive skins and produce trees and orchards of
thought. William of Occam and Duns Scotus were key thinkers in this early phase
of liberalism. Occam and Scotus had a great respect for the senses (and what
could be known through them), and they had a certain cynicism about what the
mind could know. The nominalist tradition did put forward the importance of
individual things and the uniqueness of the particular. It was this philosophic
tradition (good in its time as an important corrective to the collective and
transcendent) that opens up the drama of liberalism. It is important to note,
at his point, that the Anglican movement (Radical Orthodoxy) holds firmly to
this axial point. John Milbank’s Theology and Social Theory and Catherine Pickstock’s After Writing:
On the Liturgical Consummation of Philosophy
argue that the roots of modernity and the liberal ethos can be found in the
Late Medieval world. The Radical Orthodox movement, interestingly enough, has
some affinities with the perspective of C.S. Lewis. Lewis thought that with the
coming of the Reformation (that was heralded by certain Late Medieval
intellectuals), western thought had a decisive and significant turn on the
human journey.
If
William of Occam, Duns Scotus and nominalism can be seen as a Act One in the
liberal drama, then the Reformation takes us to Act Two. The ideas and notions
that were in the air in the Late Medieval era took a more formal and material
form in the Reformation period. There is little doubt that many important
theologians and activists in the 16th century appealed to liberty, equality and
individual conscience for their authority in contrast to the church,
institutions and tradition. It was this appeal to these principles (even though
the Bible was used as an external form of authority) that truly sets the
liberal tradition in motion. Those like Luther, Calvin and the Anabaptists
turned against the historic Roman Catholic Church, and even though they
justified their actions in reference to the Bible, the deeper principles that
animated their decisions were conscience, liberty and individualism. If it was
simply a matter of returning to the Bible as the source and fount of authority
to solve the problems of the Roman Catholic Church, then the Reformers should
have agreed on things. But the fact that the Reformers soon disagreed on how to
interpret the Bible meant that some other authority was at work. And this new
authority was the primacy of the individual, in conscience, choosing what
he/she thought was the best interpretation of scripture. As each and all
applied such implicit and liberal principles to the religious life, it was just
a matter of time, of course, before the church would splinter and fragment in
many different directions. It is in this sense that the Reformation embodies
Act Two of the liberal drama. The fragmentation of the church in the 16th and
17th centuries is the beginning of pluralism and multiculturalism, and the
politics of identity that underwrite both pluralism and multiculturalism are
the liberal principles of equality, liberty, conscience and individuality.
It was
just a matter of time before the Bible and the Church waned as matters of
primary interest in Western thought and civilization, but the principles
initiated by the Reformers came to dominate the landscape of the time. Act
Three in the liberal drama emerged in the latter half of the 17th century. The
English civil war and the Thirty Years War in Europe raised two important
issues. Those who often claimed to have absolute knowledge differed on who had
it, and each and all who claimed to have such knowledge could be quite vicious
and violent with those who differed with them. Many thinkers at the time came
to the conclusion that knowledge was just a matter of perspective (both
knowledge in the area of science and knowledge about human nature), so it was
much saner and wiser to accept this fact and avoid absolute claims. Human
nature was now seen as a blank piece of paper waiting to be written on or a wet
and sticky piece of wax awaiting an imprint and seal. The Bible and the Church
might fulfill some private and subjective needs, but the real authority was the
individual and their right to life, liberty and estates. The human journey was
an open-ended project, and there were little or no boundaries or precedents to
tell a person how to live such a journey or what trail and path to hike. The
principles, though, of individuality, liberty, equality and conscience had
become the new dogma and creed. The content of such principles could be decided
as each individual saw fit. This hands off approach in the area of religion,
economics and the arts moved the liberal drama to yet its new scene and Act.
The
Enlightenment of the 18th century yet further consolidated the liberal way and
franchise. Act Four was well under way, the crowds were riveted in their seats,
and most applauded the drift and direction of things. Those who had argued for
liberalism in the 16th and 17the centuries were mostly of the emerging middle
class. It was this class that longed to exert their liberty and individuality
over and against the upper classes, the monarchy and the lower classes. The
rise of Christian denominations in the 16th and 17th centuries appealed to
liberty, conscience, equality and individualism to oppose and distance
themselves from the historic forms of Christianity such as the Roman Catholic
and Church of England traditions. The Puritans on the Continent, in England and
in the USA all turned to the liberal principles of conscience, liberty and the
rights of the individual in good conscience to chose and live the good and holy
life. This is why it is important to see Puritanism as the parents of
liberalism. Many think that Puritanism and liberalism are at odds and enemies.
Nothing could be further from the truth. The very principles that Puritans
appealed to are the founding principles of liberalism. The Enlightenment of the
18th century used the principles that were claimed by many of the Reformers and
the Puritans to undermine the religious zeal and commitment of the Reformers
and Puritans. The Enlightenment in England, France and the USA (and other
places for that matter) argued that each and all should have the freedom to
question both Christianity and the middle class. If the Reformers and Puritans
used the principles of liberty, conscience, equality and individuality to
deconstruct and undermine the historic church, then the Enlightenment used the
same principles to undermine the Reformers, the Puritans and Christianity. Why
should not each and all have the freedom to chose the faith of their choice?
What made Christianity any better than any other religious tradition? Truth is
just a matter of perspective and relative (is this not what the Reformers and
Puritans had essentially created with their fragmented church and different
interpretations of the Bible?). The Enlightenment further argued that freedom
should also be for the working and lower classes, the peasants and the people.
Freedom should be for one and all both in a religious and political sense, and
no one should have the right to oppose or resist such a noble and ennobling
idea. The roots of liberalism were going deep, and the tree was growing a
strong cultural trunk and spread out many a tenacious branch. It now had
become, for most, the only perspective to adopt and bow before. Who could
possibly stand against this mighty force? Surely only reactionaries and those
nostalgic for an idealized past could say No to such a progressive and forward
way of looking at life.
The
Victorian era opened up Act Five in the Western drama. The idea of progress and
evolution were very much the air breathed by many at the time. The past was the
dark ages, and the new was the best and better. This notion of history as
progress and the idea of historicism dwelt in a symbiotic relationship. If the
past was a backward time, and we were all products of our time, and the only
real way to live in time was to exercise our liberty in the best way possible,
then there were little or no restraints to define how we were to use such
freedom. The Victorian era lingers for some as the last vestiges of the dying
Puritan ethos, but, in fact, the Victorian era in England, and the Romantic
movement on the continent drove forward the language of liberty and
individuality to new heights and with a greater passion. The Bible, the Church
and the Middle Class (who had initiated the liberal way) were being bypassed. A
new generation of liberals were emerging that were, in a religious sense, open
to all faiths (and no faiths) and, in a political sense, urging and arguing for
liberty of the lower classes. Workers of the world unite. You have nothing to
lose but your chains. The content of liberty, equality and fraternity was
changing, and those appropriating it changing, but the principles set forth by
William of Occam, the Reformers, the Puritans and the Middle Class remained the
same. Ideas do have consequences, and it often takes centuries to fully play
such ideas out, but the fully-grown plant is in the seed. The end is in the beginning.
The drama does move ever forward and onward. The actors and actresses are more
sure of their parts as one scene opens and unfolds into another scene.
The
twentieth century ushered us into Act Six in this drama. The principles of
liberty and equality, individualism and conscience still shaped how the play
was to be directed and the actors and actresses were to act their predictable
parts. Women used such liberal notions to fight for the vote, and many urged
the state to get involved so one and all would have, at least, equality of
condition and opportunity. The more sensitive artists probed the nature of
conscious, unconscious and subconscious life, and human nature was seen as a
mysterious and questionable project. Impressionism in painting and a literary
stream of consciousness came to dominate the day. Each and all were expected to
dive deep and probe the mysteries of the inner depths. The turn to the inner
life was part of the search for the authentic, real and genuine self as opposed
to the fictions and conventional ego that many were content to live with and
from. Just as the Puritans of old had used the language of conscience and
liberty to interpret the Bible and live a life of holiness, the modern 20th
century liberal used the language of conscience and liberty to interpret the
text of the soul and live a life of authenticity. The principles remained the
same even though the texts used were different and the content of things found
went in different directions. And, just as the Reformers and Puritans differed
on how to interpret the Bible, and created different churches and traditions to
reflect this reality, so the modern liberal differed on how to interpret the
needs and longings of the soul, and different tribes, clans and the media
worked together to create holy sites for such seekers to turn to in their
search for meaning and purpose.
The
latter half of the 20th century and the early part of the 21st century have
been called the postmodern era, a period that has brought to an end the meta-narratives,
foundational and structural thinking. This, in many ways, brings us into Act
Seven in the liberal drama. This is a period of time in which human nature and
human identity is defined in a variety of ways. Many argue that we should have
the right to make ourselves into anything we wish, just as we should have the
right to pick any food from the shopping mall or wear any clothes we wish. We
can change our image of ourselves and our identity as we change clothes, and
who is to say which garment is the best to wear. All is a matter of opinion and
perspective, is it not? The culture wars that take place between many liberals
and conservatives these days is often not so much about the underlying
principles that have defined and shaped these traditions. It is more about how
and where these principles are applied and the new water poured into such
vessels. Even though the language of post modernism is really just an extension
and variant of liberalism, conservatives and liberals do clash on what form
liberalism should take and why. We do need to remember that Occam, Scotus and
nominalism, the Reformers and the Puritans, the Middle Class revolution and the
Marxism were about extending the franchise of freedom in new areas. The
Reformers and the Puritans wanted the freedom to think and worship as they
pleased in opposition to the historic church, and they were for a market
economy in opposition to mercantilism. But the principles appealed to were
liberty and conscience. The church was fragmented, a hands-off approach to the
economy was held high. Holiness and the godly life were at the core of this
position. Our postmodern liberals appeal to the same principles, and rather
than holiness, happiness and authenticity are their ends and goals. Liberty is
now extended to such areas as gay rights, abortion, feminism, alternate family
values, spirituality and the right to create identity as each and all see fit.
Ideas do have consequences, a seed does, in time, produce a fully-grown plant,
and the ideas and principles of Occam, nominalism, the Reformers, the Puritans,
Locke, Smith, Paine, Mill and many others have come home to roost. Act Seven in
the liberal drama is playing itself out in a predictable way and manner, and
the language of rights, diversity, process, tolerance, pluralism and openness
is very much the sacred speech, script and shibboleths of the liberal drama.
We do
need to ask ourselves, though, this simple question. What is the good in
liberalism and what are its limitations? If we cannot question the liberal
drama and play, what sort of literary critics are we? If we do not know how to
raise critical questions, have we not been taken in by the matrix of
liberalism? Liberals often lament the way propaganda works to seduce and numb
the mind and imagination, but how many liberals are aware of how liberal
propaganda might do the same thing? Is it possible to think outside of the
matrix, and, if so, how is this to be done? There are those like Francis
Fukuyama who have argued that we have come to the end of history, and it is the
liberal principles that have brought us thus far. It is these principles,
Fukuyama argued, that now shape what is good, true and acceptable in our global
village. All must conform to these principles if they ever hope to get a
hearing in the courts, public places and universities. The task, now that we
live at the end of history (in terms of an intellectual journey) is just to
apply these sacred principles in the world of history. The text has now been
settled on. We just need to apply it to the practical sphere of life. But, are
we at the end of history, and, is possible to challenge the creed and dogma of
liberalism?
IV.
The
End of Liberalism and the End of History:
Philosophical Probes
Charles Taylor is very much a leading apologist of
the Liberal Enlightenment project. Taylor has walked the extra mile, to define
and defend liberalism, against its postmodern aberrations on the one hand, and,
in opposition to the Classical tradition, on the other hand. Taylor, at his
sensitive, insightful and incisive best, does offer the reader the most nuanced
and most attractive versions of liberalism. It is then to Taylor we will turn to
send out some philosophical probes about the problems and weak chinks in the
liberal agenda.
Taylor’s Sources of the
Self: The Making of the Modern Identity
(1989), and his smaller and more popular missive on the same subject, The
Malaise of Modernity (1991), do much to
articulate both the most attractive and compelling arguments for the liberal
way, and some of the frets and worries of a thoughtful liberal. Sources
of the Self is a rich read in the historic
western journey, and the way those within this journey have attempted to
understand and define the self. Taylor does, regrettably so, distort and
caricature the Classical tradition somewhat, but this is a predictable tendency
of most liberals. They do need to justify their principles, prejudices and ideas
in opposition to what went before them, so they often do so by doing a
questionable read of such a tradition. Gadamer, MacIntyre or Jaeger are much
better and more dependable guides into the Classical ethos. Sources
of the Self is divided into five sections:
1) Identity and the Good, 2) Inwardness, 3) The Affirmation of Ordinary Life,
4) The Voice of Nature, and 5) Subtler Languages. In each of these chapters,
Taylor probes and inches ever nearer and closer to the core of the liberal
tradition. It is important to note, both by way of conclusion in Sources of the
Self and throughout The Malaise of Modernity, that Taylor does have concerns
about the way liberalism can be used, abused and misused. He comes as a critic
of those who abuse and misuse the liberal agenda, but he also, in a limited
sort or way, comes as a probing critic of those who are uncritical fans and
boosters of liberalism.
There are many knockers of
liberalism at the present time. Taylor is not one of them. There are many
uncritical defenders of liberalism. Taylor is not merely one of them. Taylor,
in fact, concludes Sources of the Self with ‘the conflicts of modernity’. The
liberal tradition both within itself and in the contest between conservatism
and liberalism does have its problems, and these must be faced. What, then, are
some of the conflicts within the modern liberal agenda? There are six we will
briefly touch on.
First, liberalism emerged
in history in response to and as a reaction to a certain read and
interpretation of conservatism. Liberals often know what they want to be free
from, but when it comes to defining what they want to be free for, the content
of such choices tends to be a rather open ended project. It is true, of course,
that liberalism did put forward as its leading principles such notions as
liberty, choice, equality, reason/imagination, the rights of the individual and
the quest for meaning and happiness as guiding ideas. But, such principles when
disconnected from the Good can come to be defined in a variety of ways. This,
then, is the first dilemma of liberalism, and it is this dilemma that sets it
apart from the Classical way. Liberalism tends to be quite shy and hesitant
about suggesting that there is a Good (in both a metaphysical and ethical
sense) that one and all can know. When notions such as the Good, the True and
the Beautiful are both privatized and relativized, then they can be defined as
each and all see fit. It is this liberal fear and suspicion of saying much
about the Ultimate (or reducing it to a mystery that each and all perceive and
define in their own way) that makes liberalism a chameleon like agenda that can
become whatever an age wants or wishes it to be.
Second, the liberal notion of the self, identity or
nature tends to lack boundaries that could give focus and direction to the
self. Liberals have tended to argue that the self is a project in the making,
that we begin as a blank pieces of paper, and what is written on us and what we
write on the page of our emerging journey is the self. This is why the language
of process, pilgrimage, dialogue, diversity and many other terms are the lingua
franca of this tradition. The strength of liberalism is its openness, but its
limitation is its lack of boundaries. The Classical notion of order, rooted and
grounded in the Good, comes as an affront to the Liberal emphasis on liberty
and freedom. Liberalism has a difficult time in understanding boundaries for
the self for the simple reason, for most liberals, the very notion of
boundaries and limitations are the problem. Liberty often stands in stark
contrast to the repressive nature of boundaries and limitations. Liberty is
seen as the good (regardless of the content of liberty), and order is seen as
the enemy of liberty. It is this overemphasis on liberty, and this tendency to
see order as the problem that is a problem in liberalism as it seeks to
interpret the self and articulate some sort of ethical position.
Third, the liberal
principles of liberty, choice, equality, individualism, fraternity (solidarity)
and the role of reason/intuition as a means of knowing do raise some troubling
questions. The collision, for example, between the rights of the individual in
their longing for liberty and the rights of the community and the common good
often collide. There are the principles of liberalism; then there is the
prioritizing of such principles. There have been, since the birth of
liberalism, these tensions, conflicts and collisions within the liberal family.
The leftist tradition will tend to prioritize the communal and fraternal side
of liberalism, and the rightist tradition will play up and prioritize the
liberty aspects of liberalism. The problem for liberalism is this. Given the
principles that define liberalism, what criteria does the liberal use to
prioritize such principles and why? This deeper criteria goes to the very
unresolved heart and core of the liberal way. Liberalism itself cannot and does
not have the resources to resolve such a dilemma, and this is why liberalism
(in its right, left and centrist traditions) lives in such unresolved conflict.
Fourth, and this is a
telling point, liberals long on the one hand to be open to one and all, seek to
be understanding and honour perspectives and different ways of being. This
approach, of course, often takes a person to the place in which listening,
hearing and respect for the other is held high, but such a position makes it
difficult to state and argue that there are rights and wrongs, goods we should
desire and things we should avoid. The more we argue that there are standards
one and all should heed, hear and abide by, the more we take a position that
there are limits to hearing, listening and dialogue. This dilemma has been
worked out, in an interesting way, in Taylor’s life and thought. Taylor was
most active in the 1950s and 1960s as a guiding light of the New Left in both
England and Canada. In fact, Taylor was the president of the NDP in the 1960s.
Taylor’s The Pattern of Politics (1970)
was a blistering attack and assault on Trudeau and Trudeau’s brand of
liberalism. Taylor was, in short, committed to the New Left liberal standards
of fraternity (solidarity) as a guiding principle and light from which liberty
would emerge. All must be free so that each may be free. Taylor, at this point
in his life and journey, did not suggest that all philosophical and political
perspectives (and the parties that embodied them) were just a matter of where a
person stood, how they saw things. Taylor thought and acted as if certain
things were better than others, and, as such, it was important to act and live
from such realities. As the 1970s and 1980s took their toll on Taylor, he
moved, increasingly so, into the area of hermeneutical suspicion. This means
that much is just a matter of how we see, and how we see and perceive things is
conditioned by where we stand. This new stance by Taylor means that he does not
have quite the same passion he once had for firmer political positions. His new
position is one of suspicion about those who take positions of firmness and
clarity. This dilemma for Taylor is well articulated by Ronald Beiner in Philosophy
in a Time of Lost Spirit: Essays on Contemporary Theory (1997). Beiner did his Ph. D. with Taylor, and in a
chapter in the book, ‘Hermeneutical Generosity and Social Criticism’, Beiner
probes this dilemma in Taylor. Taylor, the social critic in the 1950s-1960s has
become Taylor political fence sitter in the 1970s-1980s-1990s as he has moved
in the area of hermeneutical generosity.
The more all is seen as a matter of perspective, the
more difficult it is to be committed about much other than perspectives. The
more a person is committed to what is perceived as the better or the good, the
less inclined they are to reduce most things to an equal level of perspectives.
Liberalism does dwell in this intellectual dilemma. The agnosticism built into
its very fibre does, when day is done, make it difficult to take anything,
other than diversity and pluralism, agnosticism and perspectives with much
seriousness. It is this dilemma that often confounds the liberal. There is the
human desire to know and believe some things are better than another, but the
liberal undercuts and undermines taking such commitments with too much
seriousness. This then leads to a sort of sitting on the fence and a paralysis
when it comes to committed action. We purchase tolerance at the price of
relativizing all things. When this occurs, much is dumbed down to the trivial
and silly. Taylor would have his questions about this, but, at a higher level,
most liberals are very much trapped in Taylor’s dilemma.
Fifth, liberals hold high
certain principles that I have mentioned above, but what is most interesting
(given the commitment to critical thinking) is that many liberals simply do not
question the principles themselves. If asked about the limitations of liberty,
equality, choice, individualism, identity as task in the making, most liberals
go mute and silent. Many liberals are quick and hasty when it comes to exposing
the limitation of conservatism, but they tend to be slow off the mark in
unmasking the principles of liberalism. This is called the mote and beam
syndrome. It is one thing to see the beam in the eye of the other. It is much
more difficult to see the beam in one’s eye. The fact that liberals often can
and do not do this should raise some questions in the mind of the thoughtful. A
good question that each and all should, in a regular way, pose to liberals is
this: what are the weakness and limitations of the liberal way (both at the
level of principle and practice)? If this question cannot be adequately raised
or answered, then liberalism is no different than the conservatism or
fundamentalism it often differs with. It is often this inability of liberals to
critique themselves that is most illiberal.
Sixth. Liberalism is often weak and wanting when it
comes to offering any sort of content to the principles of liberalism. It is
this silence on questions of content (or this openness to any sort of content
poured into such vessels) that does need to be raised. If, at the level of
liberal principles, questioned need to be raised, it is equally important to
ask the liberal what criteria is used to decide the content to be poured into
principles of liberty, choice and equality? It is these criteria, again, that
do raise some troubling questions for the thoughtful liberal.
In sum, if we dare to send
some philosophic probes the liberal way at the end of history, we do need to
question the dogmatic commitment to certain principles, the problems of how
such principles should be prioritized and why, questions about the sources of
the self, the tension of thinking there is a good yet being agnostic about the
good and the need to articulate some positive content and grounding for the use
of freedom.
V.
The
End of Liberalism:
Contemplative Probes
The liberal notion of the self, as I mentioned above,
tends to lack a certain depth and inner structure. The self, within such a
tradition, can and has been seen as a blend of the rational and conscious life,
a deeper sub an unconscious mythic life. Needless to say, the life of the body
and its many needs and wants are part and parcel of this bundle of needs,
longings, wants and hungers for meaning and purpose. Liberals tend to shy away
from positing anything foundational, structural and of knowable meta-truth.
This, it is often argued, limits freedom and leads to repression. The will to
be free, and to define freedom in whatever way is in the interests of he/she
who longs for such freedom is the code of the liberal way.
The contemplative traditions
in most of the major and minor religions of the world do differ with the
liberal project in this regards, and this is why many who have come to the end
of the liberal way often turn to the contemplative traditions in either the
west or east in search of greater depths. The Orient posits the notion that
there is a moral law in the cosmos, and to the degree this law is heeded and
attuned to the good life can be known and lived. The Indian Tradition calls
this dharma and the Chinese Tradition
calls this the Tao. The
Abolition of Man, by C.S. Lewis, walks the
extra mile to highlight how many of the Major Religions of the share a common
ethical core. The Western Tradition holds high the idea of natural law, the
Decalogue and the Beatitudes. Each of these Traditions point to a deeper moral,
metaphysical and ontological order in the universe, and they, as one, warn one
and all that those to fail to heed and respond to such an order will do hurt
and harm to all and one. What is this order, and how does it relate to an
understanding of the self?
The Western Tradition,
from its origins and beginnings, has argued that humans live in a divided self.
Plato compared this to the dark and white horse that the chariot rider must
keep under control. Augustine distinguished between caritas (the good within which is love and leads towards
unity) and cupiditas (the dark
and shadow side within the leads towards fragmentation and disunity). The
Fathers of the Church made a distinction between the image of God within each
person (that could not be eradicated and was good) and the likeness of God
within each person (that had been tarnished and distorted what humans were
meant to be). The Greek philosophers made the distinction between eros (that force within that moved all things to the
fullness of Being) and thanatos
(that death instinct and power within all things which sought to thwart and
negate the longings of eros, and
drove those who heeded the dark side to non-being). Rousseau made the
distinction between healthy self love (amour de soi) and unhealthy self love (amour propre). Thomas Merton summed up these differences quite
well when he said,
Contemplation is precisely
the awareness that this ‘I’ is really ‘not I’, and the
awakening
of the unknown ‘I’ that is beyond observation and reflection and is incapable
of commenting upon itself. Our external, superficial ego is not spiritual. Far
from it, the ego is doomed to disappear as completely as smoke from a chimney.
It is utterly frail and evanescent.
This distinction between
the ego that is forever restless, forever hungry, forever consuming a variety
of things to fill and fulfill its nagging emptiness and restlessness has no
substance. Unfortunately, for many liberals, the ego is the alpha and omega of
identity. The flux and stream of consciousness of the ego, the random and many
thoughts and images that jump to and fro within each person, like so many
monkeys on a tree is often the material liberals work with to forge and form
the self. But, the contemplative tradition argues that if human identity is
sought at this level, restlessness and inner turmoil and suffering will be the
result.
The Indian and Chinese
Traditions take this issue to the same level. What are dharma and the Tao? Such ideas are surely more than a sweet moral code of nice and
pleasant behaviour that boy scouts and girl guides might doff their dutiful
caps to. Both of these traditions argue and insist, and demonstrate through a
variety of practical spiritual disciplines, that the ego is empty, and until we
see it as such, we doom ourselves to a frantic search for meaning. It is by
seeing the emptiness of the ego, it is by seeing all as maya and sunyata that a new fullness emerges. But, and this is the key, the ego must
die, must be let go off, must disappear, must be detached from for the deeper
reality to be known and experienced. The liberal tradition tends to have a weak
and limited understanding of anything deeper than the ego, and this is its
weakness and limitation. Liberalism was formed and forged on the anvil of the
ego, and it has tried, century after century, to set free the ego, through the
principles of liberty, equality, choice and individualism. But, the very means
used works against the deeper ends that the liberal seeks to attain. Dharma and the Tao will not accept those who come with the pack of their ego full. All
must be let go of if and when insight and wisdom is to be found. John of the
Cross insisted that until the nothingness (nada) of the ego was seen for what it is, the fullness (todo) of real life would never be known. There is an
instructive Zen parable that nicely sums up this issue.
Nan-in, a Zen Master, had
a university professor visit him. Nan-in served the professor tea, and he kept
filling the cup until the tea spilled over the rim. The startled professor
watched until he could no longer contain himself. ‘Can’t you
see that the tea
is spilling all over me?’ he cried out. Nan-in stopped pouring, then he said,
‘You are like this cup. You are so full of your knowledge, opinions,
speculations. How can I show you real Zen and your true self unless you first
empty the cup of the stale water of your ego?’
It is at the point when
liberalism has come to the end of its tether on the question of ego, the self
and identity, it could despair or continue to run round and round on the
treadmill but go nowhere. There came a point for many liberals in which the
liberal quest for the self had to go to deeper levels. It was in this
frustration with the limited understanding of the liberal notion of the self
that there emerged, in its most recent phase, the turn to the East. The 1950s
signaled a significant season in the most recent turn by many liberals to the
East for a deeper spiritual source. What makes this such a liberal turn is that
most of the major liberal themes are at work, but the themes appear at a deeper
level. The deeper level, as I mentioned above, tends to focus on the self
beyond the ego. Much must die, much must be left behind, many an addiction and
attachment must be bid adieu to. But, at the far end of the ego, what sort of
self do we find? Are all religions saying much the same thing at this juncture?
This is where the liberal Enlightenment project kicks back in yet again.
Those such as Huston
Smith, Ram Dass, Robert Aitkin, Philip Whalen, Gary Snyder, Alan Ginsberg and
many other dissatisfied liberals that turned East in the 1950s, and remain
teachers to many today are pluralists. Thich Nhat Hanh, the Dalai Lama, and in
a lesser and lighter way, Bishop Michael Ingham’s, Mansions of the Spirit, are gurus for many, and their appearances and books
are best sellers. Why is this? They very much play into the western liberal
commitment to religious pluralism. This has become the new shrine that many bow
at, and not to bow at such an altar is to be banished from the liberal
Sanhedrin. The argument is fairly simple, and it goes like this. True and
authentic religion is about spirituality, contemplation and mysticism. Mystics
are all of one accord, so this argument goes, that we must all die to live. The
ego and shadow side must be faced and not allowed to dominate the inner life.
What, though, is on the far side of the ego? Do all mystics and contemplatives
agree about the nature and substance of the new being, and do they all agree
that mystics agree about this? The establishment liberal mystics all tend to
see each and all religion as being different and diverse on an exoteric level,
but on the inner, esoteric and mystical level, each and all sit side by side
and agree. But, do all mystics agree about what the self is like beyond the
ego, and what the nature of union with God (if there even is a God to be united
with) is like? A serious study of the mystics both within each tradition and
between traditions indicates this is not the case. Such an statement comes as
an affront to those who argue, whether through the Parliament of World
Religions such as Wayne Teasdale in The Mystic Heart: Discovering A
Universal Spirituality in the World’s Religions (1999) or Phil Cousineau’s edited conversations with Huston Smith, The
Way Things Are: Conversations with Huston Smith on the Spiritual Life (2003) that this is the case. Liberals are back in
the game again. Just when we think they have left, they return with
Enlightenment mystical pluralism and syncretism well in hand. We only need to
read Lessing’s Nathan the Wise to
get a sense of déjà vu.
Many a thoughtful and
engaged Christian has attempted to heed and hear the best from the
contemplative and mystical East. The dialogue between Thich Nhat Hanh/ Daniel
Berrigan in The Raft is Not the Shore: Conversations Toward a
Buddhist/Christian Awareness, the Thomas
Merton/D.T. Suzuki dialogue in Zen and the Birds of Appetite,
Speaking of Silence: Christians and Buddhists on the Contemplative Way (edited by Susan Walker) and the more recent
dialogue between Robert Aitken/David Steindl-Rast, The Ground We
Share: Everyday Practice, Buddhist and Christian tend to point the way to points of concord, convergence and
commonality within and between these contemplative traditions. Bede Griffiths
remains a guru to many Christians, also, for the way he has done much the same
thing for Christian-Hindu contemplative dialogue. Books such as The
Marriage of East and West and
Return to the Centre do tell their own
compelling tale. This approach, of course, works very well within the liberal
agenda. But, we might want to ask this rather simple question: do these
traditions (and the mystics and contemplatives that live from within them), at
the deepest level, agree on what lies on the far side of the ego? Is there a
self after the letting go of the ego? What are the contours and horizons of
this self? Is there even a self to speak of, or is this not yet another
illusion we need to rid ourselves from?
Griffiths, Berrigan,
Merton and Steindl-Rast have walked a generous and gracious distance to find
the points of commonality with contemplatives and mystics in other religious
traditions. The approach used is popular for the simple reason it is the child
of the Enlightenment pluralist creed of the time. Dare liberals, though,
question such a dogma, and what is the fate of those who do? Do all mystics
agree that at the centre and core all is one and the same? This is just not the
case. We do not need to read too far or deeply into the writings of mystics
both within and between traditions to discover that their notions of the self
beyond the ego are quite different. A cursory read of Geoffrey Parrinder’s Mysticism
in the World’s Religions, R.C. Zaehner’s Concordant
Discord: The Interdependence of Faiths or
Frederick Copleston’s, Religion and the One: Philosophies East and
West to discover this elementary truth.
Parrinder, Zaehner and Copleston had the contemplative sensitivity of Berrigan,
Merton and Steindl-Rast, but they, also, were quite willing to ask questions
about points of discord and divergence between the major religions at a deeper
contemplative level. Needless to say, Parrinder, Zaehner and Copleston are not
popular within the liberal pluralist ethos in the same way the Dalai Lama,
Thich Nhat Hanh, Huston Smith, Robert Aitken, D.T. Suzuki, Gary Snyder, Allen
Ginsberg, Wayne Teasdale or David Novak are. The latter group speaks to the
pluralist spirit of the age, and the former group dares to challenge such a
perspective. It seems to me prophets and saints do not exist to baptize and
bless the status quo. They come to questions and critique such dominant
ideologies.
Liberalism (in either its
crude or more sophisticated mystical form) is very much the establishment creed
of the age. Establishment thought can be equated with Constantinianism. Those
who uncritically bow before the pluralist shrine of liberalism are like those,
in the early church, who sought to see the interests of the state and the
church as one and the same. It was the Christian mystics and prophets who
challenged such a union and synthesis. Dare they do less today?
Let us wrap up this rather lengthy paper. It is almost impossible to avoid the matrix of liberalism these days. It shapes and defines, it enframes and conditions virtually all ethical, political, religious, educational, cultural and social thought. If we have not learned to think outside this matrix, we probably have not yet learned to truly think. It is considered quite unspeakable to question liberals about the weaknesses of liberalism, but it is such raids on such unspeakable things we must do if we are ever going to be minimally alert and alive.
Comments